Translate this page:
Please select your language to translate the article


You can just close the window to don't translate
Library
Your profile

Back to contents

Philosophy and Culture
Reference:

Semantic uncertainty of the general theory of systems and problems of its interpretation and formalization

Gribkov Andrei Armovich

ORCID: 0000-0002-9734-105X

Doctor of Technical Science

Senior Researcher, Scientific and Production Complex "Technological Center"

124498, Russia, Moscow, Zelenograd, Shokin Square, 1, building 7

andarmo@yandex.ru
Other publications by this author
 

 

DOI:

10.7256/2454-0757.2023.10.44167

EDN:

JWTGNS

Received:

29-09-2023


Published:

06-11-2023


Abstract: The subject of research in this article is the question of the possibility of formalizing the general theory of systems, that is, turning it into a language for describing systems of any nature with unambiguously defined lexical units and rules. To answer this question, the author considers the phenomenon of semantic indeterminacy of languages, which ensures the flexibility of formed lexical constructions due to the multivalence of lexical units. Also the subject of the research is the practice of quoting out of context – a phenomenon, the admissibility of which is conditioned by the isomorphism of lexical constructions, as well as by the creative nature of the cognitive process, in which the result of cognition is unknown in advance, and thus the change of interpretation of the used concepts is inevitable. The conducted research allows us to state that the general theory of systems cannot be exclusively an applied theory, but should be supplemented with an ontological component. In this case, it becomes a philosophical theory, for which full formalization is impossible without loss of functionality. As a result, general systems theory must inevitably retain a certain semantic uncertainty. This uncertainty, however, can be reduced by translation into universality and generalization of concepts. Besides, it is possible and in some cases necessary to formalize separate components of the general theory of systems, in particular, its ontological component - the metaphysics of material existence.


Keywords:

general systems theory, formalization, lexical units, language, semantic uncertainty, citation, context, isomorphism, interpretation of concepts, ontology

This article is automatically translated.

Introduction

The desire to formalize the general theory of systems and turn it into a language for describing systems of any nature with unambiguously defined lexical units and rules initiated the creation of a significant number of applied versions of the general theory of systems (OTS). Among the most developed applied general theories of systems characterized by a high level of formalization should be attributed to A.A. Bogdanov's tectology [1], M.D. Mesarovich's mathematical general theory of systems [2], A.I. Uemov's general theory of systems [3], etc. 

Despite the indisputable advantages of such theories, they have not been widely disseminated and applied. The main reason for this is the inability to ensure the integrity of the system representation on the basis of such general theories of systems. As you know, the central idea of the general theory of systems is the isomorphism of forms and processes in the universe, which is an empirical confirmation of the integrity of the world. Therefore, it is the integrity of the formed model of being that is the task of the general theory of systems. On the basis of formalized (including mathematical) general theories of systems, it is impossible to ensure this integrity.

How do formalization and mathematization interfere with the holistic representation of the universe? Why does the natural human language (supplemented in some cases by the formalized language of science) cope with this task better? Confirmation of the possibilities of natural language as the main tool of human thinking is a huge array of discoveries, creative achievements born of intuition, fueled by the unity of the world, which finds its manifestation in isomorphisms, in analogies, and sometimes formalized through tradition.

The human language is not a random set of lexical units and rules, but a dynamic system that has developed and adapted to solving problems of optimal communication between people and reliable reflection of reality. Both of these tasks, considered within the framework of the knowledge system, are solved on the basis of the use of generalized concepts, qualitative descriptions, complexes of essential features for the identification of the object of cognition, etc., i.e. through semantically indefinite lexical units. Note that when we talk about "indefinite" lexical units, we mean their ambiguity, sometimes "vagueness".

Many leading researchers in the field of general systems theory believed that this theory could not be considered as part of philosophy. In particular, A.A. Bogdanov wrote "... I would doubt whether it is advisable to apply the name "philosophy" to organizational science ..." [1, book 1, p. 57]. For A.A. Bogdanov's general theory of systems (general organizational science or tectology) and a large number of other versions of the general theory of systems, this assessment probably has a right to exist. However, according to the author, this assessment is not a qualification of the essence of general system theories, but a statement of their incompleteness and incompleteness, which results in limited possibilities and, as a consequence, practical application. These incompleteness and incompleteness can be overcome by including an ontological component in the general theory of systems, which substantiates the genesis of the integrity of the universe and thereby provides the philosophical basis of the theory. The author is working on creating such a version of the general theory of systems (empirical-metaphysical general theory of systems [4]). As a result, a theory will be formed that is fully philosophical.

Formal philosophy is a direction that has been successfully developing since the beginning of the XX century (the works of D. Hilbert [5] and R. Carnap [6]) to the present time. At the same time, formal philosophy does not pretend to solve philosophical problems, its purpose is exclusively auxiliary: "... to clarify and clarify theses, accelerate the correction and improvement of philosophical and scientific theories, work more effectively with natural language intuitions, analyze the consequences of accepted hypotheses" [7]. Similarly, mathematical (formalized) general theories of systems can be useful in solving individual particular problems, but the whole variety of problems of cognition of the world (many of which are formulated with significant uncertainty, and this is normal for cognition) is not covered by available tools and methods.

In the framework of this study, we will try to answer the question about the possibility of formalization of the general theory of systems, as well as about the objective reasons that prevent formalization. To answer this question, we will consider the phenomenon of semantic indeterminacy of languages, as well as its use to expand the cognitive capabilities of the general theory of systems.

 

Semantic uncertainty of languages

The system of knowledge about the world is a model of being formed through all the tools of cognition available to mankind, among which one of the most important is the natural human language (a set of languages of different peoples, as well as the language of science common to all peoples). By necessity, the human language has been formalized to a certain extent – for each of the languages, a vocabulary and a set of rules for the formation and use of lexical units have been formed, as well as their semantics have been determined. At the same time, in order for a language to fulfill its function as an instrument of cognition, the lexical units used in it (words, phrases, established phrases, etc.) must have the ability to be used to describe objects of cognition of different nature. In practice, this ability is realized in the simplest way – due to semantic uncertainty [8].

The phenomenon of semantic uncertainty can take various forms, among which, in particular, are distinguished [9]: pragmatic uncertainty of language expression, according to which a decrease in the accuracy of expressions encourages communicants to more creative thinking and "completing cognitive gaps", as well as referential diffuseness, which consists in pointing through language expressions to a wide class of events or phenomena, the boundaries between which are not clearly defined.

Semantic uncertainty is based on the ambiguity of lexical units. The certainty of their content in practical use is ensured due to the context and nature of the relationship of lexical units [10]. The variability of the relationship of lexical units forms by means of language patterns of form or relations that characterize the described object of cognition. In this case, the identification of the object of cognition (or its properties) is carried out by comparing it with the corresponding pattern (template of forms or relationships). Thus, the ambiguity of lexical units ensures the universality of the means of description, and identification by the corresponding pattern (taking into account the context) ensures the consistency of the description.   

The futility of improving the accuracy and logical certainty of the language is well illustrated by the Ithkuil language [11], developed by the American linguist John Quijada. In this language, any ambiguity is excluded. The language is characterized by the highest phonetic complexity (45 consonants, 13 vowels in 7 tones).  There are two parts of speech in the language: word-forming and adjuncts (defining). The first ones change according to 9 configurations, 4 accessories, 4 perspectives, 6 extensions, 2 entities, 4 contexts and 2 assignments. The latter are inclined into 22 morphological categories. There are 98 cases in Ithkuil. In addition, suffixes clarifying the meaning can be added to any word (a total of 1800 different suffixes), including 14 valence suffixes, 32 aspect suffixes, 24 emotional color suffixes. The practical use of the Ithkuil language is extremely difficult. A significant part of the statements (if there is some uncertainty, ambiguity in them) is impossible in it, and those that are possible are formulated much more difficult than in ordinary language. Initially, when creating this language, it was assumed that it would allow you to express thoughts faster than ordinary languages, but this hope was not fulfilled.

Can the Ithkuil language and similar logical languages be useful? Absolutely, yes. However, their use is limited to the formalization of existing knowledge, as well as their archiving. For creativity, the usual content of which is the search for answers to finally unformed questions that are clarified in the process of cognition, such languages are completely unsuitable.

 

Quoting out of context

The experience of scientific activity, involving the preparation of publications containing references and citations of other researchers in this field, shows that quite often references and citations are used out of context, as a result of which their meaning is distorted, interpreted, and sometimes even distorted. To the greatest extent, this tendency of quoting out of context is inherent in philosophical and other poorly formalized sciences. Along with quoting out of context, there is also another related phenomenon – the use (acceptance, statement) of conclusions formulated within another context, without confirming their argumentation (conclusion, proof). In the future, by "quoting out of context" we will mean both of these phenomena.

One of the most obvious examples of "quoting out of context" is the correlation of the laws of development in dialectical materialism and Hegel's philosophy [12, p. 40]. Dialectical materialism borrows from Hegel's philosophy the laws of dialectics, deduced and reasoned in the logic of objective idealism, and transfers them into a materialistic context incompatible with idealism. At the same time, there is no new proof of the validity of the laws of dialectics, they are accepted "as is", without adjustments, with only some semantic interpretations. The question of why, nevertheless, the laws of dialectics (or, to put it more correctly in terms of materialistic ideas, the laws of development) are relevant deserves attention and will be considered further in this article.

Another example of "quoting out of context" is A. Einstein's formulation of the "Mach principle": "... the cause of inertia is the interaction of a material point with all other masses..." [13]. A. Einstein believed that in his formulation he expresses E. Mach's ideas about relative inertia, while the coincidence in Einstein's judgments and Mach on this issue exists only at the level of terminology. Speaking about inertia, each of them meant different physical phenomena by this: Einstein meant inertial mass of a body by inertia, and Max – inertial motion [14].

As an example of accepting conclusions without confirming their argumentation, one can cite the discreteness of being claimed by Plato and Aristotle, which is due to its definiteness and completeness. And it is impossible not to agree with this statement (including the materialist). At the same time, it must be remembered that Plato and Aristotle were objective idealists and by being they understood the world of ideas (forms), and not matter at all. The material world (matter), in their opinion, is becoming, i.e. it is on the eternal path to being. The world of things and bodies, in their opinion, is infinite, continuous, and therefore it is not being.

The practice of "quoting out of context" at first glance seems to be an extremely destructive phenomenon that calls into question the reliability of the knowledge obtained. But then why don't they give it up? Because to a greater or lesser extent, no scientific work is free from this practice. Indeed, only in some rare cases, subsequent scientific or philosophical research can fully rely on the previous ones, without correcting the interpretation of concepts and connections between them in them. Moreover, in those rare cases when such an adjustment does not occur, the scientific value of the work usually turns out to be low.

And there is nothing strange in this, since the formation of new knowledge is a creative process, the distinctive feature of which is the impossibility of determining the result before it is obtained. A scientist cannot know for sure what his research will lead to. And even when a scientist completes his research, the continuation of this research by other scientists will again face the lack of reliable knowledge of the expected result. Since every result of cognition is formalized in the form of concepts, the process of knowledge formation must inevitably be accompanied either by the introduction of new concepts, or (in most cases) a change in the interpretation of existing concepts.

The experience of scientific and philosophical knowledge clearly testifies to the right of the practice of "quoting out of context" to exist. According to the author, this is due to the existence of isomorphism of forms and laws in the world, manifested in all objects of cognition, including lexical constructions of various levels of complexity, which are descriptions of the relations of objects and processes in the universe. And at the same time, it is not always important in what context these lexical constructions were formed – there is a kind of equifinality [15, p. 132] in the formation of forms and connections that fit into limited sets of patterns. 

The equifinality of forms and connections corresponding to lexical constructions is due to the fact that these constructions in most cases represent open models of being. By "open" we mean models that turn out to be applicable outside the field of cognition, based on the data on which the model was created [16].

In this case, we do not consider the reliability of the model, only the ability to predict new (not embedded in the model) connections in the universe on its basis is important. The experience of cognition accumulated in the form of a human knowledge system clearly demonstrates that even erroneous theories (ideas, concepts) can serve to expand knowledge, find the right answers to the riddles of nature, which can be verified and clarified in the future [16]. Along with private scientific theories that have made a significant contribution to the development of knowledge, but were later rejected (phlogiston, hydrogen, ether, etc.), religion can also be cited as an example, which fundamentally contradicts scientific ideas, but is nevertheless relevant in terms of social and spiritual issues. 

So, the practice of "quoting out of context" and similar phenomena are permissible in cognition. At the same time, it is necessary to understand that such practice is appropriate at the stage of searching for answers, but not their argumentation and proof. The unity of the world, manifested in the form of similarity of forms and laws, equifinality of forms and connections (including in relation to lexical units), gives us an instrument of isomorphism, analogies, and deduction, through which we get "hints" about the structure of the world. These "hints", however, can only indicate the likely direction or area of the search, but do not guarantee correct answers.  

  

Requirements for the language of general systems theory

Determining the probable directions or areas of search for answers to questions about the structure of the universe based on isomorphism and the patterns of forms and relationships that follow from it is the main task of the general theory of systems [4]. Therefore, for the general theory of systems, the semantic uncertainty of language and the practice of quoting out of context are natural and organic phenomena. Naturally, as the general theory of systems develops, the language used in it can evolve, in particular, be supplemented with universal concepts corresponding to the system description. At the same time, its rigid formalization is impossible, since it would entail the complete loss of its functionality by the general theory of systems.   

The impossibility of full formalization of the general theory of systems is not a reason for refusing to formalize its individual components. One of the areas where formalization is necessary and possible is the methodology of applied system analysis. At the same time, it is necessary to understand that in this case formalization is carried out within the framework of the theory of knowledge – at the level of universal and generalized concepts, the genesis and inner content of which is either not disclosed or unknown. As a result, such generalized and formalized concepts have internal semantic uncertainty in the sense that, using them, we only roughly understand what they mean, and rarely have an idea of their ontological genesis (if they have one at all).

As an example of formalization in applied system analysis, we can cite the division of ways to solve problems into four options [17, p. 13-15]: non-interference (in the expectation that the natural course of events will lead to the resolution of the problem), partial intervention (a solution that reduces dissatisfaction, weakens the severity of the problem, but does not eliminate it completely), the optimal solution (the solution that is the best in these conditions based on the existing limitations and alternatives) and dissolution (a solution that ends with the complete disappearance of the problem and prevents the emergence of new problems). Within the framework of this classification, solutions to problems seem to be formalized, but there are many details within each of the options that need to be clarified in terms of content and implementation mechanisms.

Another area of necessary and possible formalization of the general theory of systems, which should become an integral part of the general theory of systems (at least the author in his empirical-metaphysical general theory of systems strives for this) is the ontological part of the theory – the metaphysics of material being, which determines the primary properties of being and the laws logically following from them [18]. For such properties and laws, formalization is possible and necessary, which does not imply ambiguity and semantic uncertainty. These properties and laws are not only used for cognition and description of the world, but are also the basis for the formation of the methodology of cognition within the framework of the general theory of systems.

Semantic uncertainty in the formation of the ontological basis of the general theory of systems is unacceptable for two reasons. Firstly, the area where it realizes its usefulness is the theory of cognition. Ontology serves to comprehend reality as it is, and not our ideas about it or methods of its representation in the knowledge system, and therefore does not need semantic uncertainty. Secondly, one of the tasks of forming the ontological basis of the general theory of systems (the author calls it the metaphysics of material existence) is the consistent determination on the basis of the primary properties of being (i.e. a priori knowledge) of the laws and forms logically following from them, which in the future can be used as patterns for the analysis of nondeterministic complex objects of cognition. The construction of reliable logical chains, the elements of which have semantic uncertainty, is extremely difficult because in the process of their construction, the options will multiply, going beyond the limits of the practical availability of their critical analysis.

The general attitude of the general theory of systems, conditioned by the requirement to preserve its functionality, is to preserve the natural uncertainty inherent in human languages, allowing for ambiguity, changing depending on the context, but providing flexibility and the possibility of describing objects of cognition at the stage of their incomplete certainty.

How can this general attitude be combined with the formalizations of the general theory of systems? This task is completely unsolvable, but it is possible to increase the degree of formalization of the general theory of systems. Formalization will not reduce the epistemological possibilities of the general theory of systems in the case of translation of semantic uncertainty into universality and generality of concepts. At the same time, it is necessary to understand that for a significant part of the concepts used in the practice of cognition (including with the help of the general theory of systems), such a translation is impossible. Therefore, the general theory of systems should preserve the semantic uncertainty of concepts, forms and connections in the arsenal of its tools.

 

Conclusions

Based on the reflections given in the article , the following main conclusions can be drawn:

1. The experience of creating formalized general theories of systems shows that such theories are not widely used and do not provide coverage of the entire problem of system description of objects of knowledge.

2. The limitation of formalized (mathematized) general theories of systems is due to the fact that in reality the general theory of systems cannot be exclusively an applied theory, but must be supplemented with an ontological component. In this case, the general theory of systems becomes a philosophical theory for which complete formalization is impossible without loss of functionality.

3. A necessary property of language as a tool of communication and cognition is its semantic ambiguity, which provides flexibility of the lexical constructions formed due to the ambiguity of lexical units. The certainty of their content in practical use is ensured due to the context and nature of the relationship of lexical units.

4. The practice of quoting out of context and the use (acceptance, statement) of conclusions formulated within another context without confirmation of their argumentation (conclusion, proof) is a phenomenon whose permissibility is due to the creative nature of the cognitive process in which the result of cognition is unknown in advance. As a result, the content of the concepts through which the results of cognition are formalized change their interpretation as knowledge expands. In addition, the existence of isomorphism of forms and laws in the world, manifested in all objects of cognition, including lexical constructions of various levels of complexity, makes these constructions elements of the knowledge system and allows us to consider them in isolation from the context of their formation.

5. The language of the general theory of systems, which, as we have established, should become part of philosophy, cannot be fully formalized. At the same time, the formalization of individual components of the general theory of systems is possible and even necessary. In particular, according to the author, it is necessary to formalize its ontological component – the metaphysics of material existence, which, along with practical application in cognition, also serves to define the internal logic of the general theory of systems itself.

References
1. Bogdanov, A.A. (1989). Tectology: General organizational science. In 2 books. Moscow: Economy.
2. Mesarovich, M., Takahara Y. (1978). General theory of systems: mathematical foundations. Moscow: Mir.
3. Uemov, A.I. (1978). System approach and general theory of systems. Moscow: Mysl.
4. Gribkov, A.A. (2023). Empirico-metaphysical approach to the construction of the general theory of systems. Society: Philosophy, History, Culture, 4, 14-21.
5. Hilbert, D., & Bernays P. (1979-1982). Foundations of Mathematics. Volumes 1 and 2. Moscow: Nauka.
6. Carnap, R. (2008). Philosophical Foundations of Physics: Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Moscow: LKI Publishing House.
7. Dolgorukov, V.V., & Shumilina V.A. (2021). What is formal philosophy? Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, 58(1), 235-241.
8. Brattseva, A.L. (2017). About semantic uncertainty of special lexical units. Bulletin of Moscow State Linguistic University, 6(777), 21-31
9. Iriskhanova, O.K. (2008). About types of knowledge and semantic uncertainty (case about case). Cognitive Studies of Language, 3, 148-158.
10. Motro, Y.B. (2009). Semantic uncertainty of terms in cognitive-pragmatic illumination. Bulletin of Moscow State Linguistic University, 557, 182-190.
11. Ifkuil In Russian (2023). Retrieved from https://ithkuil-rus.github.io/
12. Engels, F. (1941). Dialectics of Nature. Moscow: Gospolitizdat.
13. Einstein, A. (1965). Collected scientific works: in 4 vol. Volume 1. Moscow: Nauka.
14. Paramonov, A.A. (2018). Late collision to the history of one semantic uncertainty. Philosophical Journal, 11(4), 59-74.
15. Bertalanffy, L. (1969). General System Theory. Foundations, Development, Applications. George Braziller Inc., New York.
16. Gribkov, A.A. (2023). Problem of Loss of Integrity of Modern Philosophical and Scientific Knowledge. Philosophical Thought, 10(1-9). Retrieved from https://e-notabene.ru/fr/article_44094.html
17. Ackoff, R.L. (1999). Re-Creating the Corporation: A Design of Organizations for the 21st Century. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
18. Gribkov, A.A. (2023). The simplest material structures-consequences of the primary properties of being. Society: Philosophy, History, Culture, 6, 23-2.

First Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

The reviewed article discusses the problems of formalization of the general theory of systems. The author holds the view that such formalizations cannot be complete, however, one should strive for at least a partial solution to this problem, since any formalization increases the accuracy and correctness of the use of available knowledge. In connection with the above, I would like to recommend that the author supplement the title of the article, since it does not reflect the entire real content of the text. It seems that the following option could be proposed: The semantic uncertainty of the general theory of systems and the problems of its interpretation and formalization. The author believes that no formal language is capable of exhausting the richness of content that lives in natural languages, therefore, formalized languages can only complement and refine natural language, which will forever remain the "common basis" of all other descriptions of reality. The author of the article convincingly argues his point of view, many of his judgments seem very interesting, and there is no doubt that the reviewed article will deserve the attention of readers. In particular, the author expresses very independent judgments about "formal philosophy", believing that the desire of its founders to break the connection of "formal philosophy" with the philosophical tradition is unjustified, and under certain conditions it can be restored. Unfortunately, there are some shortcomings in the text, although, according to the reviewer, they cannot serve as an obstacle to publication, since the author is able to eliminate them in a working manner. Thus, there is a fragment in the text from which it can be concluded that Hegel presents the "laws of dialectics". ("One of the most illustrative examples, etc.") This is a misunderstanding or a consequence of the author's unsuccessful way of expressing himself; of course, there are no formulations of the "laws of dialectics" in Hegel's texts. The well-known formulas (and their names) belong to Engels, although, of course, they relate to certain components of Hegelian philosophy. There are also punctuation errors, stylistic errors, and typos in the text that need to be corrected before publication. In some cases, there are extra commas (so, already in the first sentence: "and by the rules, initiated..."; and why "initiated" if "idefix" is a masculine noun? It should also be pointed out that dictionaries (in this sense) label it as "iron.", so was it necessary to start the presentation in such an unusual way?) In other cases, on the contrary, there are no commas, for example, the adverbial phrase remained "unclosed": "speaking of "indefinite" lexical units, we mean ...". It should also be noted that the explanation itself contained in this sentence seems to be unsuccessful, it contains a tautology and hardly complements the intuitively clear "indefinite". Typos include an extra soft sign ("the author ... strives for this") or "why then ..." instead of "but why", etc. At the same time, I repeat, the article is written in good language, it is easy to read, the author has undoubted professional erudition and expresses non-trivial judgments on many controversial issues. Based on the above, I recommend publishing an article in a scientific journal.

Second Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

The presented article is devoted to the problem of formalization and mathematization of the general theory of systems and its application in various fields. The author argues that the formalization of the language of describing systems of any nature cannot contribute to a holistic ontological view of the universe, since it is clearly inferior to natural language, which, despite reflecting structures of logical thinking that can be mathematized, also has the character of semantic uncertainty. The research methodology includes the use of the results of linguistic research and criticism of the formalized theory of systems. The relevance of the article is due to the need to compare the processes of formalization with natural intelligence, which is certainly important for the future of philosophy and, in particular, ontology in the context of not only positivist concepts, in the light of pragmatics and analytics, but also in connection with the emergence of artificial intelligence and other processes caused by digitalization. However, the author himself does not formulate this connection, which could focus more on the problem of understanding the general trends of posthumanism or expand the range of the issue under consideration. The scientific novelty is determined by the criticism of the creation of formalized general theories of systems, as well as the author's argumentation of the impossibility of their wide application as an applied theory. The presentation style is strictly scientific, the article is well structured, includes a well-designed introduction and conclusion, the content fully reflects the stated topic. The goals and objectives formulated at the beginning of the article are realized in the reasoning of the author, who logically builds his argument. The conclusions are clearly formulated and numbered in the conclusion, in addition, the author offers his own solution to the problem of partial formalization of the theory of systems – the metaphysics of material existence. The bibliography includes 18 items, which is a sufficient number, the author refers to both modern sources and basic ones, highlighting the main conceptual approaches on the chosen topic. However, a question arises about the percentage of likely self-citation (articles in the bibliographic list from 15 to 18): the volume of the article is generally small, and referring to already published author's texts takes up more than a third of the article, which is unacceptable. The author does not indicate who he is referring to in support of his reasoning, which allows us to conclude that he is quoting his works. Appeal to opponents: the author of the article addresses various positions regarding the formalization of the theory of systems, critically analyzes different approaches and argues his position. The conclusions that the author comes to logically follow from the whole reasoning. It may be of interest both to the mass readership for acquaintance with the theory of systems, and to specialists in the field of philosophy. It is recommended to finalize the article in terms of reducing repetitions and self-citation from previous articles written by the author earlier.

Third Peer Review

Peer reviewers' evaluations remain confidential and are not disclosed to the public. Only external reviews, authorized for publication by the article's author(s), are made public. Typically, these final reviews are conducted after the manuscript's revision. Adhering to our double-blind review policy, the reviewer's identity is kept confidential.
The list of publisher reviewers can be found here.

The subject of the study of the article "Semantic uncertainty of the general theory of systems and the problems of its interpretation and formalization" is the general theory of systems, more precisely, such an understanding of the universe (world, being, Universe), which proceeds from the unity of all its processes and the possibility of formulating the most general laws of the universe, in relation to which all known laws of specific sciences will be only private cases of their manifestations. According to the author, the main task of the general theory of systems, a task that has not been solved at the moment, is to form an integral model of being. All available attempts to solve it by creating the most formalized description language (A.A. Bogdanov's tectology, M.D. Mesarovich's mathematical general theory of systems, A.I. Uemov's general theory of systems) are unsuccessful. The author wonders about the reason for this fiasco. The research methodology combines general scientific methods of abstraction and idealization, mental modeling and the hypothetical-deductive method with the inherent philosophy of "thinking in limiting, absorbing concepts, asking, which in every question, and not only ultimately asks about the whole" (M. Heidegger). The author believes that it is philosophy, and not specific sciences or their integration, that is able to overcome difficulties in building a general theory of systems. The relevance of the presented research is related to the fact that the question of creating a general theory of systems remains open and the author's attempt to overcome the incompleteness of building this system by including an ontological component in the theory, substantiating the genesis of the integrity of the universe and thereby providing the philosophical basis of the theory, looks promising. The scientific novelty of the article is related to the analysis of language in relation to the construction of a general theory of systems. The author evaluates the heuristic potential of formalized languages with their accuracy and unambiguity of lexical composition and grammar, on the one hand, and natural languages, the main feature of which is ambiguity (semantic uncertainty), on the other. And prefers natural languages. The style of the article is typical for scientific publications in the field of humanitarian studies. The author is a little too keen on special terminology, which, however, is justified by the subject of the study. In the text of the article, clear formulations of key theses are combined with logically consistent argumentation. The structure and content of the work fully correspond to the stated topic. The author examines it consistently through such sections as: "Semantic uncertainty of languages", "Quoting out of context", "Language requirements of the general theory of systems". The strength of natural languages in the article recognizes their ambiguity, and therefore "flexibility", adaptability to the display of changing reality. The author focuses on the analysis from "non-contextual citation" - a situation in which the transfer of conclusions, patterns, judgments formed in relation to a specific aspect of reality turns out to be possible to apply completely to another or even other aspects of it. According to the author, this proves the existence of isomorphism of forms and laws in the world. The bibliography of the article includes 18 titles of works by both domestic and foreign authors devoted to the problem under consideration. The appeal to the opponents is fully present, starting with the discussion of the possibility of formalizing the language of description of the general theory of systems, including the analysis of semantic uncertainty, quoting out of context, the possibility of partial formalization of the general theory of systems. The article has deep philosophical significance for understanding the process of realizing reality, building its explanatory models, therefore, despite some complexity of the issues discussed, one can hope for the interest of a wide range of philosophers, social philosophers, and theorists of science in it.